Abstract
In this essay, I will propose an alternative
interpretation to Aristotle’s virtue politics that seeks to redefine ‘citizen’,
‘state’, and ‘community’, as well as their relationship to each other. In
Aristotle’s ethical and political works, he writes that in order to live the
best and most virtuous life possible the individual must participate actively
as a citizen within the political community. He asserts that man is a political
animal by nature and we achieve goodness and cultivate our souls by living
within a state. Aristotle outlines a close relationship between the individual
and the city, so much so, that all values are considered only in what benefits
the higher interests of the government. I argue the State is detrimental to the
individual and impedes the development of virtuosity through political
activity. I will provide the evidence of Socrates’ trial at Athens to exemplify
the destructive effects of the pre-eminence of government and law to human
character. Further, I will present several texts, grounded in the theories of
mutual aid, anarchism, and worker organization to bring clarity to my
redefinition of political activity without government interference as the ideal
environment for soul-making.
Introduction
Aristotle affirms that all human associations are
created as an endeavor to achieve goodness. The state, or political community,
is the utmost good that encompasses all other human associations. If political community is the final or
highest good, it follows that a person can only become virtuous by actively
participating as a citizen in a state. Aristotle’s definition of state differs
from our modern conception. He defines the state as composed of citizens, who
by nature, live together to satisfy the needs of living. Humans are unable to exist independently of
the community and are therefore drawn to the political life. Although Aristotle’s ideal state is one that
borders on philosophical anarchism, for he concedes that though it would be
best to not be ruled at all, for Aristotle, political life requires an organized
government. This is not dissimilar to
the modern conception of the political state- I will refer to this state with
the capital ‘S’ –which is a designated nation or territory under one
government. The identity of Aristotle’s
ideal State is synonymous to its constitution and government. Further, Aristotle’s definition of citizen is
not limited to a mere populace of voters, as is contemporarily recognized, but
of an active ruling democratic body in which all appropriate and able persons
must reside within the public sphere.
The duties of a citizen are met by being engaged in a position of public
office and by maintaining steadfast dedication to the administration of justice
and the well-being of the State. A
citizen is evaluated and given privileges based upon their support of the
State. The sacrifice of the individual to the well-being of the State is the
crippling flaw of Aristotle’s virtue politics. Aristotle’s great-souled man is
one who has developed their soul to the pinnacle of human goodness. A person
may become independently virtuous, but in order to be excellent beyond
criticism, virtue is dependent on community. The faculties of reason, the most
revered quality of human kind, and that which separates men from animals,
requires a social setting for development. While this is true and agreeable in
and of itself, the communitarian political life that Aristotle demands of
citizens begs the question of individual rights. Aristotle’s theory forfeits
individual happiness for the interests of the State, restricts people from
living a private life, and secures citizens a sentence of mandatory loyalty to
a government and law, even if it is unjust.
If the State is the ultimate authority, the human soul has no room or
potential for development and ultimate goodness is limited. In what follows, I will attempt to show that
Aristotle’s conception of virtuous soul-making within community requires a
stateless society.
The Individual, the State, and the Community
For a community to be good, the people within a community must be good.
A community is a body of persons living together collectively in a particular
area or society. Human development is a cooperative endeavor and requires a
completely autonomous society. If the people composing a society are
unfulfilled individually, the entire body of the association will be
underdeveloped. When the State’s
livelihood supersedes that of its citizens, those persons living under its
higher rule, the individual cannot grow. Realized human potential demands that
a certain environment be kept. When flaws in human character are present, the
individual is not at fault. All men and women possess latent potential to
become healthy in spirit and mature in personality. It is only when social
conditions are ill, that human behavior, subject to a corrupt external
environment, becomes despoiled in turn. When the State imposes restrictions on
human impulse by exercising ultimate control and dictating what behaviors are
appropriate within the boundaries of a community, the in-born faculties of true
human character are distorted. For this reason, people are unable to engage in
positive relations with others. The prominent anarchist and feminist of the
20th century, Emma Goldman, wrote extensive volumes on the injurious effects of
the State on the individual. She firmly held that social relations could begin
only when individuals had grown to know themselves. True human consciousness
required an awakened awareness of one’s desires and a firm and intimate
relationship with intellectual reasoning. Goldman writes, “Poor human nature,
what horrible crimes have been committed in thy name! Every fool, from king to
policeman, from the flatheaded person to the visionless dabbler in science,
presumes to speak authoritatively of human nature. The greater the mental
charlatan, the more definite his insistence on the wickedness and weakness of
human nature. Yet, how can any one speak of it to-day, with every soul in
prison, with every heart fettered, ruined, and maimed?” (Day, 111). Goldman’s
view of human nature was undoubtedly positive and she held that until
constricting outside influences, namely the State, were completely removed it
would be impossible to fully know human character without perversion through an
environment of political lenses. Even the lowly criminal, is a man or woman,
whose erroneous offense is merely a response to a negative situation, that
twists and distorts the human spirit to act from a nature that is not inherent
to human-kind, but merely a reflection of exterior dissoluteness.
Author Janet Day, provides a thorough examination of
Emma Goldman’s conception of the individual and their negative relations with
the State that brings further clarity to the importance of the fully developed
individual to the integrity of a community. In Day’s essay, “Individual in
Goldman’s Anarchist Theory”, she outlines Goldman’s definition of
individuality. Day writes, “Goldman identifies two types of consciousness:
consciousness of self and consciousness of relations with others” (Day, 111).
Both of these fundamental components are had unanimously across all human
beings. Consciousness of self is that which the individual must strive to
recognize, to cultivate their capability to know and be conscious of others.
Lamentably, despite belonging innately to all men and women, few can realize
these critical elements of their personality under the State. Janet Day quotes
Emma Goldman in her work, and writes, “Goldman lays the blame on, “every
institution of our day, the family, the State, our moral codes, [which] sees in
every strong, beautiful personality a deadly enemy; therefore every effort is
made to cramp human emotion and originality of thought in the individual into a
strait-jacket from its earliest infancy; or to shape every human being
according to one pattern; not into a well –rounded individuality, but into a
patient work slave, professional automaton, taxpaying citizen, or righteous
moralist” (Day, 116). The groundwork for
the well-being of the State is strict adherence to the ideals of the current
social order. As these are prescribed by an entity above the individual, a
person will never come to know themselves under its might.
Day continues in her essay by illustrating what Emma
Goldman expresses to be the unrealized individual. Referred to as the mass man,
these persons are those, who under the rule of the State, have become
un-realized individuals, stricken “[with] cowardice, who fail to think
independently, and who… [are] fearful of others, which leads to the destruction
of human relations and social harmony” (Day, 117). The dignity of these
individuals has succumbed to the prescriptions of society, whether economic,
social, moral, or otherwise, and they are starved of the exceptionality of
their identities. The freedom of the mass man is diminished and their actions
are sanctioned. Dependence on and enslavement to these commandments of social
order, stifles the individual and thus the entire community becomes
stagnated. How individuals relate with
each other is solely reliant on the environment established by the State, which
is merely one that ensures the institution is able to prevail and discourages
human interaction. Day writes that Emma Goldman’s believes the conditions
necessary for realizing human potential are only possible within an anarchist
community. Anarchism is a society, without any coercive institutions, in which
people voluntarily associate and cooperate for the benefit of the entire
populace. Free of the interference of the State, society will no longer exist
to enslave man but will exist to benefit him. Day concludes that, “Since
anarchism, which is against all forms of law, authority, and coercion, needs
people to be strong in mind and spirit so they may live in harmony, and for
society to be orderly and peaceful, self-directed individuals are a critical
component of its success” (Day, 123). Clearly, for a healthy community to
sustain goodness, the individual must first be satisfied in spirit.
Socrates and the State
The premier example of an individual being forfeited
for the sake of the State can be seen in two of Plato’s essential works, The
Apology and the Crito. To begin with, The Apology is Plato’s account of
Socrates’ trial against Athens in which he attempts to defend himself against
the charges of corrupting the youth and recognizing gods outside of those
approved by the city. He professes that he will speak honestly to the jury and
attributes his actions to having been influenced by the Oracle at Delphi. It
had been his divine duty to question the wisdom of men. Socrates does not deny
that his accusations are unwarranted. He says, “I do not think, men of Athens,
that it requires a prolonged defense to prove that I am not guilty of the
charges…you know that what I said is true…that I am very unpopular with many
people. This will be my undoing, if I am undone. This has destroyed many other
good men and will, I think, continue to do so. There is no danger that it will
stop at me” (Plato, 26) Socrates might
be admired for nobly accepting whatever punishment the jury may order,
regardless of his innocence, but he defends his submission to an unjust State
to be for the health of the institution and city itself. This is a ridiculous
act that serves to sacrifice his individual worth to the higher command of the
State, which has been shown to be naught but a construct of moral superiority
and control. Socrates does not admonish the jury for their final verdict to
convict him of his crimes. He says, “It is not the purpose of a juryman’s
office to give justice as a favor to whoever seems good to him, but to judge
according to law, and this he has sworn to do. Clearly, it should be a penalty
I deserve…to suffer or to pay because I have deliberately…neglected what
occupies most people: wealth, household affairs, the position of general or
public orator or the other offices, [and] the political clubs and factions that
exist in the city” (Plato, 31-32) Socrates explains that if the law were
perhaps different in Athens, the trial would not have persisted for so long and
his acts would not have been deemed condemnable.
In the Crito, Socrates’ reasons for submitting to
the will of the jury are further outlined. The Crito is a dialogue between
Socrates and a friend, Crito, who has come to help him flee from prison. This
exchange occurs in the hours before his imminent execution. Socrates argues
that to escape from prison would be unjust, regardless of his innocence, as he
would be violating the social contract between himself and the city of Athens.
He says of the State, “You must either persuade it or obey its orders, and
endure in silence whatever it instructs you to endure, whether blows or bonds,
and if it leads you into war to be wounded or killed, you must obey. To do so
is right, and one must not give way or retreat or leave one’s post, but both in
war and in courts and everywhere else, one must obey the commands of one’s city
and country, or persuade it as to the nature of justice. It is impious to bring
violence to bear against your mother or father; it is much more so to use it
against your own country” (Plato, 45). Socrates avows that the law is the final
word and that to run away would be to violate your responsibilities as a
citizen and renounce the authority of the city. He refuses Crito’s offer to
evade death and is ultimately executed.
Several authors attempt to refute Socrates’
validations for obedience to the law of an unjust city. The following works of
Nathan Hanna and Bai Tongdong well articulate my argument that an individual
should not remain dutiful to a bad State, nor is their worth determined by
obligatory political duty. In his essay,
Socrates and Superiority, Hanna provides an interpretation of the Crito that
demonstrates that Socrates was a proponent of the Superiority thesis. Hanna
writes, “The Superiority thesis is the principal support for Socrates’ decision
not to escape. Socrates is thinking as follows: much of a state’s power rests
upon its perceived legitimacy…, and a state cannot continue to survive without
its power. Anything that undermines the appearance of the state’s legitimacy,
anything that undermines reverence of the state and the law, injures the state
because it undermines the foundations of its power- power the state is entitled
to have because of its superiority” (Hanna, 263). Through this argument, it can
be inferred that by defying the law, Socrates would be injuring the State by
denying its moral authority over its citizens.
For the State to be the ultimate authority, it must be composed of a
body of citizens that are submissive to its rule. In defense of the individual, Socrates might
argue that the State is entitled to its power because of an unspoken social
contract; citizens may leave the city or must follow state orders. Hanna responds,
“[Any] agreement is a product of the state’s superiority and of citizen’s
obligations of obedience to the state, not a source of them. Because citizens
are inferior to the state they have no say over the terms of the agreement…” If
the State is the ultimate moral authority the individual has no potential for
development and ultimate human goodness is limited. Further, citizens of the
State are unable to exercise political duty by scrutinizing the authority of
the city, if they are unable to question its justness. Bai Tongdong argues similarly
in his article and deems that the reason Socrates gives for not fleeing the
city is contradictory. Tongdong writes, “Socrates himself argued that one
should do the things he agrees upon with someone else; to escape means to break
the laws of the city (the agreements with the city), and thus in order not to
do evil to the city, one has to persuade it…but to render ineffective the
judgments of the city would lead to the demise of the city” (Tongdong, 387).
Socrates’ claim that the citizen must either fulfill his political obligations
to the laws of the city or incite an alternate judgment from the jury, less
harm the institution itself, is incongruous if he also believes both outcomes
will damage the State. If citizens are
to be just and in turn the city just, the virtue of both must be
questioned. The individual, the citizen,
comprises the whole, and the interests of the people cannot be sacrificed
without damaging the entire community.
Aristotle famously purports in his work, the
Posterior Analytics, a text that focuses on scientific knowledge, that Socrates
exemplifies the great-souled man. Author Jacob Howland critiques Aristotle’s
verdict in his essay, Aristotle’s Great-Souled Man. He argues that the
discussion of greatness of soul in Aristotle’s Nichomachean Ethics is not
coherent with the Socratic character. Howland writes, “The great-souled man is
characterized by heroic, superhuman, or god-like virtue, which finds its
fullest expression in a deed whereby the whole community is saved. From the point
of view of the community, such virtue possesses absolute value…” (Howland, 32).
Further, Howland explains that under Aristotle’s conception of the great-souled
man, or the megalopsuchos, to be great in soul one must not desire honor for
honor’s sake but for the greatness of all who might possess virtue. Howland
continues, “... [to be great] one must see each virtue in its own terms, and
also as a part of the whole of virtue and of our shared, political life”
(Howland, 30). If virtues can only be discerned when observed within “the whole
of which they are parts”, the political sphere, then Socrates cannot possibly
be the megalopsuchos (Howland, 30). Socrates, though depicted in Plato’s
dialogues to seek wisdom only for the sake of the good and not personal gain,
lived a private life and was not politically active. Additionally, if
great-souled men gain honor by benefiting the community, Socrates’ subservience
to an unjust State perpetuated further harm to the entirety of Athens by
legitimizing its authority to repeatedly damage individuals.
Mutual Aid Theory and Community Building
Human development has undoubtedly been shown to be a
cooperative undertaking. Russian born anarchist and sociobiologist, Pëtr
Kropotkin, developed a theory of evolution that is based not in egoism, but the
belief that human activity is driven by true human cooperation. This theory is
known as mutual aid. Kropotkin’s scientific writings and animal research lend
to a vision of human development that further strengthens evidence for the
intimate nature of community building. Many years spent in exile for his
activism in the anarchist/communist movement offered Kropotkin the time
necessary to study natural species and his findings back these claims. He
argued that a species’ sociability was indispensable to their survival. From
his observations Kropotkin wrote, “[it is society that] enable[s] the feeblest
insects, the feeblest birds, and the feeblest mammals to resist or protect
themselves from the most terrible birds and beasts of prey; it permits
longevity, it enables the species to rear its progeny with the least waste of
energy and to maintain its numbers albeit a very slow birth rate” (Glassman,
396). Author Michael Glassman’s essay, “Mutual Aid Theory and Human
Development”, aims to shine more light on Kropotkin’s work and argues for the
necessity that the theory resurface in contemporary thought. Glassman explains,
“Kropotkin’s definition of sociability is the animal’s need for associating
with its like. The animal loves its community for community’s sake; and it is
within this community of peers that the animal finds its true ‘joy of life’
(Glassman, 393). Human communities are produced naturally from an inborn need
for the expression of sociability. If the community suffers, joy of life will
cease.
The greatest threats to a society are natural checks
that Kropotkin calls “species hostile.” Glassman writes that Kropotkin’s most
important point is that, “…the major threat to organisms are not other
organisms but a highly variable ecology” (Glassman, 400). In the natural world,
changes in food sources and the expansion or decrease of territories can have a
powerful influence on a population. The extraordinary quality that separates
men from their animal counterparts is their “ability to cultivate, and
maintain, unique, complex social organizations” (Glassman, 398). In turn, it is
the higher system of social and organizations that are at risk to become the
natural checks that are detrimental to a society. Glassman continues,
“Kropotkin saw the development of complex human society as being at odds with
ethical and cooperative behavior. The more complex the society, the more
complex, the barriers, the more opaque the connections between activity and
community” (Glassman, 395). Glassman likens the natural phenomenon of animals
that will stampede to their deaths merely to maintain the organization of the
herd, to humans who will tolerate the abhorrent acts of infanticide or female
genital mutilation merely to maintain the structure of their social
organization. Kropotkin’s theory provides a response to the obstacles that face
human societies. He affirms that pro-social activities, any action that
benefits the livelihood of a society, come from the community itself. Glassman
explains, “Individuals…engage in pro-social activity if they feel a member of
that community and through membership an obligation to maintain that community”
(Glassman, 410). For Kropotkin, this altruism is thus inborn within human-kind
to the point that feelings of sociability are synonymous with community
building.
Kropotkin’s sociobiological work did not end with
the study of animal relations but extended to an applied understanding of
relations within primitive tribes. John Slatter contributes to the conversation
with his essay, “P.A. Kropotkin on Legality and Ethics”. He explains that
Kropotkin’s theory of morality asserts that under-free association in a
stateless society, ethical feelings arise in men, producing higher moral
sentiments. The argument here is that only in an anarchist society would true
moral code be established without obligatory currents and become
“merely…relations between individuals” (Slatter, 263). Kropotkin did not
believe the intellectual atmosphere needed for the development of free
character was unobtainable. In fact, Kropotkin states, that tribal communities,
functioning without interference from
the unwarranted economic expenses and social demands of the State,
needed only “minimize conflict between individual members of the tribe [by
developing] characteristics such as honesty, loyalty, a sense of fairness, a
readiness, to share, and inclination to hospitality, and the practice of
chastity in sexual relations” (Slatter, 266). The incentives to maintain these
feelings are synonymous with the need to maintain the community. It was only in
inter-tribal relations that disputes are tense, as the community’s well-being
is not at stake and no connection to the other tribe is felt. Political writer
and anthropologist Pierre Clastres writes, “For the State to appear there would
have to exist a division of societies into antagonistic social classes…” This
follows from Kropotkin’s tribal theory in which the State is unnecessary so
long as the bonds between and within communities are strong.
Worker Organization
If the virtuous person is one who acts according to
what contributes to the overall good, a model for the depiction of such
achievement might be seen in the example of a cooperative worker
organization. Maria Homiak argues for
this in her essay, “Politics as Soul Making”, and believes that Aristotle’s
virtue politics are best explained through such a model. Friendly feelings arise when we actualize our
faculties for human reason. In a
workplace in which better conditions are met for some, but not others, it is
not in the interests of the privileged to attend to the plight of the few. When, however, work is transformed from a
focus on the production of the goods for individual profit and salary to one
where all members may freely discuss the association, each worker can express
their human faculties and become confident in their individuality. Workers now
desire the good, the benefits of their work, for everyone, so that happiness
and motivation are sustained to continue to increase production rate. Homiak
writes, that “feelings of solidarity and camaraderie among members… [and the]
workers’ ability to express their human powers in action, coupled with the
democratic conditions inside the workers’ association where each member
conscientiously and manifestly does his part, can upset competitive feelings by
removing the bases for inferiority and superiority” (Homiak, 175). If these
egalitarian conditions are extended to a community, as I argue, alienation
between members will subside and strengthen the whole of the social
relationship. This is not dissimilar to Aristotle’s theory of the political
life, one that through shared deliberation the human good can be promoted. The
workers now have the ability decide how to bring the good to themselves and
others.
Conclusion
According to Aristotle, humans are social and
political animals who desire and thrive in the company of other people. People
become virtuous and grow intellectually and in spirit through political
activity. I have argued that the State, an organized, coercive, body of
government, is unnecessary to human societal life. Political activity is, then,
best defined as human interaction in a community setting, without exterior
authoritative control in the environment, and for the benefit of the entire
populace. Citizens are the precious individuals that encompass a community and
define its quality. For a society to be good and virtuous, it is critical that
the people within a community be given the opportunity to fully develop their
human essence, express their individualism, and awaken their innate
consciousnesses. In contrast, when the State is the moral authority in a
society, everyone suffers. Humans are unable to become virtuous when limited by
prescribed social doctrines and mandates. In an environment subject to
government authority, the State sets an illusionary bar of ultimate goodness
that cannot be surpassed by the mere faculties of its ‘lowly’ citizens.
Socrates’ trial at Athens exemplifies the injustice the State can inflict on an
individual. When society removes the State, true human character ceases to be
distorted by its destructive influence and the entire community thrives.
In this essay, I have offered the theory of
anarchism, a free and voluntary society, to demonstrate the ideal environment
for human flourishing. The theory of mutual aid, in which individuals benefit
from a voluntary association with other individuals, in a community without
centralized control, would best reveal the inborn nature of humans to others and
relations would flourish. An instinctive trait within animal species is to live
within a community to increase the ‘joy of life’ in a way that cannot possibly
be achieved individually. Primitive societies, like tribal groups, have shown
that life without the dangers of the State is the best possible existence.
Further, these demonstrate that when a community works as a cooperative body,
the individual develops. This is a cyclic process. Neither the individual, nor,
the community can be sacrificed if ultimate goodness and virtue are to be
achieved through political activity.
Additionally, I have provided the model of a worker organization as a
small scale example to illustrate the benefits of human interaction. I conclude
that Aristotle’s political theory remains a critical component to understanding
what makes a community most virtuous, and should remain to be considered, but
with the State in the equation, his proposition falls short.
Works Cited
Clastres,
Pierre. "Society Against the State." Clastres, Pierre. Society
against the state: essays in political anthropology. New York: Zone Books,
1987. 189-218. [1]
Day,
Janet E. "The 'Individual' In Goldman's Anarchist Theory."
Pennsylvania State Univ. Pr. (2007): 109-132.
Glassman,
Michael. "Mutual aid theory and human development: Sociability as
primary." Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour (2000): 391-412.
Hanna,
Nathan. "Socrates and superiority." Southen Hournal of Philosophy
(2007): 391-412.
Homiak,
Marcia L. "Politics as soul-making: Aristotle on becoming good."
Philosophia: Philosophical Quaterly of Israel (1990): 167-193.
Howland,
Jacob. "Aristotle's Great-Souled Man." The Review of Politics (2001):
27-56.
Plato.
"Crito." Cooper, John M. Plato: Complete Works. Indianapolis:
Hutchinson , 1997. 37-48 . Print .
Plato.
"The Apology." Cooper, John M. Plato: Complete Works. Indianapolis:
Hutchinson , 1997. 17-46.
Slatter,
J. "P.A. Kropotkin on Legality and Ethics." Studies in European
Thought (1996): 255-276.
Tongdong,
Bai. "What to do in an unjust state? On Confucius' and Socrates' Views on
Political Duty." Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy (2010): 375-390.
No comments:
Post a Comment